4 The Hole Argument and Some Extensions 38
After defining geometric and algebraic structures, a space is defined as a set of points with a geometric structure that is invariant under some group of transfomations of its points. Then I discuss product and quotient spaces, fibered spaces, and theories based on these spaces, in particular permutable and generally permutable theories (Section 4.1).Up to this point, the only structures discussed have been relations between the elements of a set. But all definitions are still applicable – appropriately modified, of course – when additional structures are introduced. In particular, the case of most physical interest is that of geometric object fields defined on a differentiable manifold (Section 4.2). They provide the framework for coordinate-independent definitions of covariant and generally covariant theories, followed by a precise formulation of the of the original hole argument against general covariance and of the way to avoid its conclusion, discussed informally in Section 2.
Then I discuss fiber bundles, which consist of a total space, a base space, and a projection operator. Under certain circumstances, the base space may be defined as the quotient of the total space divided by an equivalence relation defining its fibers (Section 4.3) This approach allows a more precise formulation of Einstein’s vision of general relativity, discussed informally in Section 3.2.
Finally, the distinction between natural and gauge natural bundles is discussed, and between the concepts of covariance and general covariance when applied to theories defined on each type of bundle (Section 4.4).
A number of philosophical concepts used but not defined in this section, such as: intrinsic and extrinsic properties, internal and external relations, and quiddity and haecceity, are discussed in the Appendix B.
4.1 Structures, algebraic and geometric, permutability and general permutability
Consider a set of elements
,
,
, etc., together with a set of relations
between its
elements.39
There is a major distinction between a geometry and an algebra:
Geometry:
In a geometry, the elements of












Obviously, is the maximal possible automorphism group; so a study of its subgroups and
their relation to each other is equivalent to a study of all possible geometries on
and their relation to
each other.
Algebra:
In contrast to a geometry, in an algebra each element (symbolized by



Coordinatization:
Since Descartes introduced analytic geometry, it has proved convenient and often necessary to apply algebraic methods in the solution of geometrical problems. This is done by a coordinatization of the geometry (see Weyl, 1946, for this term): A one-one correspondence is set up between the points of the geometry and certain elements of an appropriately chosen algebra. This coordinatization assigns to each point

Permutations and the basic identity.
There are two distinct ways in which the assignment of all admissible coordinates to each point of a geometry may be accomplished.- Active point transformations: Keep the coordinate system fixed,
, and permute the points of the geometry:
,
.
- Passive coordinate transformations: Keep the points of the geometry fixed,
, and carry out an admissible coordinate transformation of the elements of the algebra:
,
.
The terms “active” and “passive” refer to the effects of a transformation on the points of the geometry. A passive coordinate transformation is an active transformation of the elements of the algebra.45
Two active permutation groups of any geometry have already been introduced:
, the group of all permutations of the elements of
;
, the subgroup of
consisting of the permutations that belong to the automorphism group
of a particular geometry
.
Relations may also be permuted. Let symbolize a relation between the set
of all points of
.46
Consider a permutation of the elements of
. Define the permuted relation
as follows:
holds iff
does. When a permutation
is carried out,
the relation
will be said to be “carried along” if it is also permuted into the relation
.47
It follows that, if is valid, then so is
.
The basic identity for the group of all permutations
.
By virtue of the intrinsic homogeneity of its
points, a geometry 













Equivalence relations and quotient maps.48
An equivalence relation


















Product sets and quotient sets.
Given two sets












In various contexts, “mappings” might also be called functions, transformations,
or operators. Homomorphisms, isomorphisms, homeomorphisms, diffeomorphisms,
continuous or differentiable maps will be more attached to certain classes of mappings,
which “preserve” certain structures on the sets which are their domains and ranges
(Hermann, 1973, p. 3).













This “passing to the quotient” is a way of defining new spaces and mappings that is very important in all of mathematics, particularly in algebra and differential geometry. (Hermann, 1973, p. 5).
This possibility allows us to realize Einstein’s vision of general relativity (see Section 3.2), which in this
context is simply: If no , then no
. We can define the mapping or morphism
from
to
,
, which projects each element
of
into the element
of
corresponding to
the equivalence class that includes
. Conversely a section of
is an inverse mapping
from the
point
of
to a unique point
in the equivalence class of
that maps into that point of
, with
.
So far, these concepts can be applied to any set. If is a geometry with automorphism group
, it
is referred to as a
-space (see Neumann et al., 1994
, pp. 74ff). The equivalence relation is said to be
-invariant if, whenever
holds for two points of
, then it follows that
for
all
. Consequently, the action of an element
on
preserves the orbits of
but permutes them; so all orbits, henceforth called fibers, must be isomorphic to what is
called a typical fiber. The quotient set
is itself a
-space called the quotient
space.
Fibered or fiber spaces.
A fibered space consists of a total space





















A fiber bundle consists of: 1) a total space
, divided into fibers by an equivalence relation
, all of these fibers being isomorphic to a typical fiber
; 2) a base space
that is isomorphic to the
quotient
; and 3) a projection operator
that takes each point of its domain
into the
point
of its range
that corresponds to the fiber including
. A section of the bundle is a
mapping
that takes each point
of its domain
into a unique point of its range,
consisting of the set of fibers of
. The point of
on the fiber
over
is symbolized by
. If
has the automorphism group
, the action of an element
on the points
of any section
will result in a new section
; symbolically:
. So, given one
section
, the action of the elements of
produces a whole equivalence class of sections
.
Theories, permutable and generally permutable.
A theory of a certain type is a procedure for producing models of that type. A particular theory of that type is a rule for selecting a subset of these models. One type of theory is defined by the choice of a fiber bundle with automorphism group


On the other hand, plane analytic geometry includes a choice of origin, unit of length, and a pair of
rectangular axes. So all of its assertions are still permutable; but some of them include references to the
origin, axes, etc. We can distinguish, for example, between a circle of radius centered at the
origin, and one of the same radius centered at some other point. So plane analytic geometry is a
permutable theory, but not generally permutable. The reason, of course, is that the choice of
a unique preferred coordinate system converts the Euclidean plane from a geometry into an
algebra.
4.2 Differentiable manifolds and diffeomorphisms, covariance and general covariance49
For the space-time theories forming the main topic of this review, is often a four-dimensional
differentiable manifold
; and the analogue of
is
, the diffeomorphism group
consisting of all differentiable point transformations of the points
of
. Any given, fixed geometric
structures defined on
, such as a metric tensor field, will be symbolized by
; they represent the
analogue of the relations
. The
-geometry of
is also defined by the invariance of these
)
under the action of some Lie subgroup
of
. In other words,
plays the role,
analogous to that of
, of the automophism group
of the
-geometry of
. And just as in that case, here every
-space can also be defined as a quotient or orbit
space:
Every -space can be expressed as in just one way as a disjoint union of a family of
orbits. (Neumann et al., 1994, p. 51)
Just as in analytic geometry, one may set up ordinary and partial differential equations
for various particles and fields on . Denote a set of such geometric object fields on
collectively by the symbol
, and consider the effect of an element
on
.50
From the definition of a geometric object (see Schouten, 1954, pp. 67–68) it follows that if
,
then
.
Geometric quantities form an important subclass of geometric objects which includes all tensor fields.
Their transformation law under is linear and homogeneous in the components of
and
homogeneous in the derivatives of
.
In both Galilean space-time (see Yaglom, 1979) and in special relativistic space-time (Minkowski space),
is a ten parameter Lie group. Four of these parameters generate spatial and temporal translations of
the points, making these space-time geometries homogeneous. And in both, the six remaining
parameters act at each point of space-time: three generate spatial rotations and three generate
“boosts”, making both space-times non-isotropic. But they do so in different ways because their
“boosts” differ: For Galilean space time, they are Galilei transformations that preserve the
invariance of the absolute time. For Minkowski space-time, they are Lorentz transformations that
combine spatial and temporal intervals into an invariant, truly four-dimensional space-time
interval. Both of these groups are subgroups of
, the group of four-volume-preserving
transformations.51
And both theories have a homogeneous, flat affine connection in common that is the mathematical
expression of the Newton’s first law of inertia. Its invariance group is
, which is a subgroup of
.
Newtonian gravitational theory, in the form which incorporates the equivalence principle, preserves the
global space-time structure of Galilean space-time, but abandons the homogeneous flatness of the
affine connection in favor of a non-flat affine connection that is the mathematical expression of
the dynamical inertia-gravitational field. This field is non-homogeneous, but its compatibility
with the space-time structure requires that locally it remain invariant under , which
means that its globally automorphism group must be
, the group of unimodular
diffeomorphisms.
General relativity similarly abandons the homogeneous flatness of the affine connection in favor of a
non-flat affine connection that is the mathematical expression of the dynamical inertia-gravitational field.
But, in order to preserve its compatibility with the special-relativistic chrono-geometry expressed by the
metric tensor, the latter must also become a dynamical field. It preserves the local space-time structure of
the special theory at each point. But globally both dynamical fields must have automorphism groups
consisting of diffeomorphisms of , the space-tme manifold, now itself no longer globally fixed.
Traditionally,
, the full diffeomorphism group, has been assumed to be the correct
automorphism group for general-relativistic theories. However, there are good arguments for
restricting this group to
, the group of unimodular diffeomorphisms with determinant
one.
But first some definitions are needed (see, e.g., Wikipedia: Group action). The action of is said to
be effective if its identity element is the only one that takes each point into itself: That is, if
,
and
is such that
for all
, then
, the
identity element of
. The action is transitive if
is a map onto
that connects any
two of its points: That is for any two points
, there is always a
for which
.
The stabilizer group at a point
of
is the subgroup of transformations
of
that leave the point
invariant: That is,
if and only if
.52
Since
is a Lie group,
is a closed subgroup at each point of
and these stabilizer groups are
conjugate subgroups of
. Indeed,
is isomorphic to
; so one may actually define a geometry
by the pair
, where
is a closed subgroup of
.
The action of is free or semiregular if its stabilizer group is the identity: That is, if
for
some point
, then
, the identity element of
; equivalently, if
for some
, then
. For example, the translation groups discussed above act freely on Galilean and special relativistic
space-times.
Now we are ready to return to the question of automorphism groups for general relativistic theories. The
action of the stabilizer of on the tangent space at each point
of
is
, the
group of all linear transformations at
. But consider the objects defining the geometry of a
general-relativistic space-time with
: Again, if one wants to preserve the four-volumes of space-time,
which are needed to formulate meaningful physical averages, one must restrict these transformations to
, the group of 23 special linear transformations with unit determinant. The linear affine connection
at
, which represents the inertio-gravitational field, is only invariant under the subgroup
, the group of affine transformations with unit determinant. And the invariance group
of the metric tensor, which represents the chrono-geometry, is even further restricted to the
pseudo-orthogonal subgroup
of
. In short, globally physical considerations
suggest the need to start from
as the automorphism group of general-relativistic
theories.
So physically, overshoots the mark by allowing non-unimodular transformations, i.e,
transformations with any value of their determinant at a point. Geometrically, they correspond to similarity
transformations, which preserve the shape but not the size of four-volumes in space-time. Usually, one
“compensates” for this unwanted change of size by introducing tensor densities: When appropriate weights
are introduced for various tensors, these densities can undo the effects of the size changes produced by
non-unimodular transformations.
However, one may simply start from as the automorphism group. The action of its
stabilizer on the tangent space at each point of
is
, the maximal symmetry group that
preserves the size of four-volumes, thus avoiding the need to introduce densities, among its many
other advantages (see Stachel, 2011
; Bradonjić and Stachel, 2012
). For much of the following
discussion, however, the distinction between
and
is inessential, so I shall
continue to discuss
, and only point out the distinction at some places where it is really
important.
Symmetry transformations:
By definition,









Passive coordinate transformations and the trivial identity:
Since it is no more than a re-labeling of its points, any admissible passive coordinate transformation has no effect on a geometry (see Section 4.1). However, if one restricts the group of coordinate transformations to a subgroup of those corresponding elements of the automorphism group of the geometry, then there is an isomorphism between this subgroup of passive coordinate transformations and the group of active point transformations defining the geometry. Hence, it is possible to reformulate any statement about the geometry in terms of relations between the coordinate components of the geometric object fields




Basis vectors and a coordinate-independent formulation of the trivial identity:
Geometrically, a coordinate system corresponds to the choice of a holonomic basis










![Φ[e(x)]](article411x.gif)
![Λ [e (x)]](article412x.gif)












![Φ [e (x)] = ′ΦD [′eD (′x )]](article425x.gif)
![Λ [e(x)] = ′ΛD [′eD (′x )]](article426x.gif)


Covariance and general covariance:
Suppose we perform the push forwards and pull packs on the geometric object fields


![Λ[e(x)] → Λ [e (x )]](article432x.gif)
![′ Φ [e(x )] → ΦD [e(x)]](article433x.gif)
![′ Φ [e (x)] ⁄= ΦD [e(x)]](article434x.gif)
![Φ [e(x )]](article435x.gif)



![Φ [e (x)]](article439x.gif)
![′Φ [e (x)] D](article440x.gif)
A covariant theory is generally covariant under the -geometry’s automorphism group if an entire
equivalence class of its mathematically distinct models corresponds to a single physical model of the
theory.
4.3 Fiber bundles: principal bundles, associated bundles, frame bundles, natural and gauge-natural bundles 55
An ordered set of basis vectors at a point of
is called a linear frame, and the set of all such
linear frames at a point of
constitutes one fiber of the bundle of linear frames over
. As
Kobayashi explains, the bundle concept can be used to formulate any geometry on
as a
-structure:56
Let be a differentiable manifold of dimension
and
the bundle of linear
frames over
. Then
is the principal fibre bundle over
with group
. Let
be a Lie subgroup of
. By a
-structure on
we shall mean a differentiable subbundle
of
) with structure group
.
(Kobayashi, 1972, p. 1).
Such a fiber bundle formulation of geometries has several crucial advantages:
It makes evident the fundamental distinction between vertical geometrical quantities, such as metric
tensors, that live on the fibers of the bundle; and horizontal geometrical objects, such as linear affine
connections, that serve to connect these fibers. This is the case whether the metric and/or connection are
fixed and given components of ; or are components of
, themselves subject to dynamical field
equations.
It enables us to go from global to local formulations of background-independent
theories, such as general relativity, in which the global topology of the base manifold
cannot be specified a priori, because it differs for different solutions to the field
equations.57
Fibered manifolds
The concept of fibered spaces for a set, discussed in Section 4.1, can now be applied to differentiable manifolds (see Section 4.2). After a fibered manifold is defined, the important cases of principal bundles, vector bundles, natural bundles and gauge-natural bundles and their physical applications are discussed, stressing the importance for general relativity of quotient bundles and local considerations.
A fibered manifold consists of a total manifold
, a base manifold
, and a projection
operator
.
is a differentiable manifold, the points of which,
,
, etc., are
grouped into fibers by an equivalence relation
between its points.
is also a differentiable
manifold, the points of which are symbolized by
,
, etc. The fiber over
is symbolized by
. Note that, if the relation
is given initially, sometimes the base manifold
may be
defined as the quotient of the total manifold
by
; in other words as the
orbit space of
(see Sections 4.1 and 4.2). But the situation is generally somewhat more
complicated:
Usually, when symmetries and invariance groups are considered, a problem reduces to the corresponding orbit space, and therefore the structure of these spaces has to be investigated. This structure theory is quite complicated in general, since these spaces usually are singular spaces and not again manifolds. In fact, only if the action of the Lie group is free (i.e., all isotropy subgroups of single points are trivial), the resulting orbit space bears a manifold structure and forms together with the manifold and the quotient map a principal fiber bundle, whose structure is well known. More often, the orbit space admits a stratification into smooth manifolds with an open and dense largest stratum, the set of principal orbits…. This stratified space can then be treated almost like a manifold when taking special care. The existence of such a stratification is usually shown by proving the existence of slices at every point for the group action (Schichl, 1997, p. 1).
I shall assume that – as in general relativity – in any theory considered, the quotient space is either a manifold or a stratified manifold; and that any local solution to its field equations can be extended to a global solution.58
A fiber bundle is a fibered manifold in which all its fibers are isomorphic to a typical fiber , itself a
manifold; that is, for all
,
. Suppose
is
-dimensional and
is
-dimensional One
can always introduce a local trivialization of the bundle: Let
be an open subspace of
. Locally, the
total space
is a product space
), and one can introduce
variables
as local
coordinates of a point
of
, and
variables
as coordinates of a point
of
.
So
) is coordinatized by the
coordinates
) of a point
of
lying on
the fiber
over the point
. Let
be a Lie group of diffeomorphisms that acts on
.59
The action of an element
on the point
of
is symbolized by
.
Two subgroups of are especially important:
- The base transformations (diffeomorphisms of
) that do not affect the fibers:
.
- The pure fiber or pure gauge transformations on the fiber at each point:
.
Both of these are included in a third subgroup:
- The fiber-preserving transformations:
.
If is a connected Lie group, all of its actions can be constructed from iterations of the action of its
Lie algebra, composed of its infinitesimal generators: The vector fields
on
, each of which generates
a one-parameter group of point transformations, or flow, on
. Locally
may be written in terms of
the coordinates
:
The generator is called:
Horizontal if , i.e., it generates only base transformations.
Vertical if , i.e., if it generates only pure fiber or pure gauge transformations.
The flow generated by will be fiber preserving if and only if
.
Natural bundles:
A fiber-preserving diffeomorphism projects naturally into a unique diffeomorphism of the base manifold


Principal bundles, associated vector bundles:
If the the typical fiber






4.4 Covariance and general covariance for natural and gauge-natural bundles
The use of fibered manifolds allows a precise formulation of the concepts of covariance and general covariance for any physical theory; and of the hole argument for background-independent theories, and even – with appropriate modifications – for some partially-background-dependent theories.
4.4.1 Fiber bundles needed in physics
Every natural physical theory can be formulated in terms of some natural geometric
object(s)61 that lives on an appropriate
fibered differentiable manifold,62
the nature of which depends on these geometric object(s). If the theory is defined on a differentiable
manifold that is the quotient of the fibered manifold
divided by the equivalence relation
defining the fibration,
; then there is an operator
, projecting each fiber onto the
corresponding point of
:
. Since the fibered manifold represents a natural object, there is a
one-one correspondence between fiber-preserving diffeomorphisms of
and diffeomorphisms of
.
A number of most important gauge natural theories cannot be so formulated, but require the broader concept of gauge natural bundles for their precise formulation. Indeed, every classical physical theory can be reformulated as the jet prolongation of some gauge natural bundle by adjoining the derivatives of the geometric object fields to the original bundle.63
4.4.2 Background-dependent theories
A theory based on such fixed -fields on
is called background-dependent, with
as its symmetry
group.64
Any geometric object fields
can then be introduced on this fixed-background space-time together
with a set of field equations governing their dynamics, which generally involve some or all of the
.
In many theories, the fixed geometric object fields on consist of a vertical chrono-geometric metric
tensor on each fiber and the corresponding horizontal inertio-gravitational linear connection. Any
non-gravitational theory can be formulated on a fiber bundle associated with the principal bundle
determined by the metric and connection: The
break up into two subclasses: The fields of massive
objects (such as charged bodies) are represented by geometric quantities living on the vertical fibers; and
the gauge fields transmitting the forces between these objects (such as the electromagnetic field) are
represented by verical connections along the fibers; these connections are only fixed up to some group of
gauge transformations.
4.4.3 Background-independent theories
In the case of general relativity and other background-independent theories (such as the coupled
Einstein–Maxwell equations), reduces to the identity and there are no fixed background space-time
structures on
.
is chosen as
in the usual formulations; but, as suggested in
Section 4.2,
, the unimodular subgroup, may be chosen. In that case, the space-time structures
subdivide further: The pseudo-metric splits into a conformal metric with determinant
and a scalar field, both of which live on the vertical fibers; while the linear affine connection
splits into a trace-free projective connection and a one form, both of which serve to connect the
fibers.
4.4.4 Gauge symmetries
To define the gauge symmetries of a certain type of theory, one must consider the sections of the
corresponding fiber bundle. A local section or global cross section
is a map
taking each point
of
or
, respectively, into a unique point of the fiber
over
.65
For each type of physical theory, a section represents a particular configuration of the corresponding
physical field. However, in theories of the gauge-field type, this representation is not unique. There is a
group of gauge transformations, each element of which maps one mathematical representative of some field
configuration into another representative of the same configuration. A gauge symmetry is an equivalence
relation on the set of sections: Two sections and
are gauge equivalent if there is a
gauge transformation taking one into the other. This equivalence relation divides the set of
all sections into equivalence classes, the gauge orbits; each section belongs to one and only
one such orbit. If the gauge group of some type of theory consists entirely of fiber-preserving
transformations, then the theory can be formulated on a natural bundle. But if its gauge group includes
non-fiber-preserving transformations, then a gauge-natural bundle is needed to formulate this type of theory
correctly.
The field equations of a particular gauge field theory serve to pick out a class of preferred
sections consisting of the solutions to these equations. For a gauge theory, these equations
must be of such a form that, if one section is a solution, then so are all members of the entire
gauge orbit of that section. In other words, the gauge transformations must form a symmetry
group of the field equations. This group is the automorphism group of the principal
gauge-natural bundle
corresponding to the theory (see, e.g., Fatibene and Francaviglia, 2003,
p. 223). Fatibene and his collaborators explain the distinction between the two types of theory
well:
The main technical difference between natural and gauge natural theories is that [base]
diffeomorphisms are completely replaced by gauge transformations. In gauge natural
theories spacetime diffeomorphisms do not act at all on fields, since the only action
one can define in general is that of gauge transformations. This is due to the fact
that although pure gauge transformations are canonically embedded into the group of
generalized gauge transformations, there is no canonical “horizontal” complement to be
identified with . …“Horizontal” symmetries, in fact, are generally associated to
physically relevant conservation laws, such as energy, momentum and angular momentum.
The definition of such quantities is almost trivial in natural theories; on the contrary, in
gauge natural theories pure gauge transformations are easily associated to gauge charges
(e.g., the electric charge in electromagnetism), while the absence of “horizontal” gauge
transformations is a problem to be solved to appropriately define energy, momentum and
angular momentum. For this reason, in gauge natural theories the dynamical connection
plays an extra role in determining horizontal infinitesimal symmetries as the gauge
generators which are horizontal with respect to the principal connection (Fatibene et al.,
2001, pp. 3–4).
While bundle formulations of the hole argument originally dealt only with natural bundles, Lyre (1999)
develops a generalized version that can be applied to gauge-natural bundles:
The generalized hole argument is motivated and extended from the spacetime hole argument …. [It] rules out fiber bundle substantivalism and, thus, a relationalistic interpretation of the geometry of fiber bundles is favored (Lyre, 1999, p. 1).
Healey (2001) also argues that “fiber bundle substantivalism …is subject to an analogue of the ‘hole’ argument against space-time substantivalism.”
4.4.5 Four-geometries and stratified manifolds
To recapitulate: The choice of a bundle selects a certain type of physical theory but does not
picked out a particular theory of that type, nor introduce any space-time structures on
or
. The
points of
form a geometry (see Section 4.1). As points of the space-time manifold, they have
quiddity but they lack haecceity: a priori there is nothing to distinguish one such point from the
others. Their automorphism group is the diffeomorphism group of
or some appropriate
subgroup, such as the unimodular group (see Stachel, 2011
; Bradonjić and Stachel, 2012
).
For example, a metric-free formulation of electromagnetic theory can be based on a bundle of
one-forms.
A particular theory is a rule for choosing a preferred class of cross sections of the fiber bundle. This rule
generally includes specification of some space-time structures on . For example, in addition to a bundle
of one-forms, source-free Maxwell electromagnetic theory, requires the specification of a conformal structure
on
.
In general relativity, an equivalence class of diffeomorphically-equivalent pseudo-metrics on a four-dimensional
manifold,66
often referred to as a four-geometry, is regarded as corresponding to a single inertia-gravitational
field. While the fiber space consisting of all four-metrics over a given manifold forms a
manifold,67
the space of all four-geometries does not form a simple manifold, but a stratified manifold. That is, it is
partitioned into slices, each of which is itself a manifold, consisting of all four-geometries having the same
symmetry or isometry group. The largest slice is the manifold of generic geometries having no nontrivial
symmetries; it contains the vast majority of geometries. Thence one descends slice by slice down to the slice
consisting of all four-geometries having the maximal symmetry group (see Stachel, 2009 and
Section 6.1).
The rule specifying the choice of a preferred class of space time structures may or may
not include some restriction on , the maximal possible automorphism group of
. Obviously, diffeomorphisms always remain unrestricted in the sense of the trivial
identity. A true restriction on the theory arises with the imposition of a finite-parameter
Lie group as the symmetry group of the class of space-time structures picked out by the
rule.68
If there are no such restrictions, the theory is background independent. If the rule includes a Lie group
involving some functions as well as parameters, the theory is partially background dependent. If the Lie
group is maximal (ten-parameters in four dimensions), then the theory is totally background dependent. If
the rule restricts the preferred class maximally, i.e., to the identity, then the theory specifies an
individuating field on the space-time, turning it into an algebra. In this formulation, the symmetry group is
included in the rule defining a physical theory, rather than being imposed a priori on the space-time
structures defined on
. This change enlarges the class of physical solutions: For example, not fixing the
global topology of
allows several possibilities for the global topology associated with a given local
metric. But this does not alter the fact that the symmetry group of the space-time structures
must be preserved by all such solutions. To what extent the hole argument applies to a non
background-independent theory depends on the degree of background dependence that has been imposed
(see Stachel, 2009
); but if a theory is background independent, the hole argument certainly
applies.